home *** CD-ROM | disk | FTP | other *** search
- SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
- --------
- No. 90-1014
- --------
- ROBERT E. LEE, individually and as PRINCIPAL OF
- NATHAN BISHOP MIDDLE SCHOOL, et al.,
- PETITIONERS v. DANIEL WEISMAN etc.
- on writ of certiorari to the united states court of
- appeals for the first circuit
- [June 24, 1992]
-
-
- Justice Souter, with whom Justice Stevens and
- Justice O'Connor join, concurring.
- I join the whole of the Court's opinion, and fully agree
- that prayers at public school graduation ceremonies
- indirectly coerce religious observance. I write separately
- nonetheless on two issues of Establishment Clause analysis
- that underlie my independent resolution of this case:
- whether the Clause applies to governmental practices that
- do not favor one religion or denomination over others, and
- whether state coercion of religious conformity, over and
- above state endorsement of religious exercise or belief, is a
- necessary element of an Establishment Clause violation.
-
- I
- Forty-five years ago, this Court announced a basic
- principle of constitutional law from which it has not
- strayed: the Establishment Clause forbids not only state
- practices that -aid one religion . . . or prefer one religion
- over another,- but also those that -aid all religions.-
- Everson v. Board of Education of Ewing, 330 U. S. 1, 15
- (1947). Today we reaffirm that principle, holding that the
- Establishment Clause forbids state-sponsored prayers in
- public school settings no matter how nondenominational the
- prayers may be. In barring the State from sponsoring
- generically Theistic prayers where it could not sponsor
- sectarian ones, we hold true to a line of precedent from
- which there is no adequate historical case to depart.
-
- A
- Since Everson, we have consistently held the Clause
- applicable no less to governmental acts favoring religion
- generally than to acts favoring one religion over others.
- Thus, in Engel v. Vitale, 370 U. S. 421 (1962), we held that
- the public schools may not subject their students to read-
- ings of any prayer, however -denominationally neutral.-
- Id., at 430. More recently, in Wallace v. Jaffree, 472 U. S.
- 38 (1985), we held that an Alabama moment-of-silence
- statute passed for the sole purpose of -returning voluntary
- prayer to public schools,- id., at 57, violated the Establish-
- ment Clause even though it did not encourage students to
- pray to any particular deity. We said that -when the
- underlying principle has been examined in the crucible of
- litigation, the Court has unambiguously concluded that the
- individual freedom of conscience protected by the First
- Amendment embraces the right to select any religious faith
- or none at all.- Id., at 52-53. This conclusion, we held,
- -derives support not only from the interest in respect-
- ing the individual's freedom of conscience, but also
- from the conviction that religious beliefs worthy of
- respect are the product of free and voluntary choice by
- the faithful, and from recognition of the fact that the
- political interest in forestalling intolerance extends
- beyond intolerance among Christian sects-or even
- intolerance among `religions'-to encompass intolerance
- of the disbeliever and the uncertain.- Id., at 53-54
- (footnotes omitted).
- Likewise, in Texas Monthly, Inc. v. Bullock, 489 U. S. 1
- (1989), we struck down a state tax exemption benefiting
- only religious periodicals; even though the statute in
- question worked no discrimination among sects, a majority
- of the Court found that its preference for religious publica-
- tions over all other kinds -effectively endorses religious
- belief.- Id., at 17 (plurality opinion); see id., at 28
- (Blackmun, J., concurring in judgment) (-A statutory
- preference for the dissemination of religious ideas offends
- our most basic understanding of what the Establishment
- Clause is all about and hence is constitutionally intolera-
- ble-). And in Torcaso v. Watkins, 367 U. S. 488 (1961), we
- struck down a provision of the Maryland Constitution
- requiring public officials to declare a -`belief in the exis-
- tence of God,'- id., at 489, reasoning that, under the
- Religion Clauses of the First Amendment, -neither a State
- nor the Federal Government . . . can constitutionally pass
- laws or impose requirements which aid all religions as
- against non-believers . . . ,- id., at 495. See also Epperson
- v. Arkansas, 393 U. S. 97, 104 (1968) (-The First Amend-
- ment mandates governmental neutrality between religion
- and religion, and between religion and nonreligion-); School
- Dist. of Abington v. Schempp, 374 U. S. 203, 216 (1963)
- (-this Court has rejected unequivocally the contention that
- the Establishment Clause forbids only governmental
- preference of one religion over another-); id., at 319-320
- (Stewart, J., dissenting) (the Clause applies -to each of us,
- be he Jew or Agnostic, Christian or Atheist, Buddhist or
- Freethinker-).
- Such is the settled law. Here, as elsewhere, we should
- stick to it absent some compelling reason to discard it. See
- Arizona v. Rumsey, 467 U. S. 203, 212 (1984); Payne v.
- Tennessee, 501 U. S. --, -- (1991) (slip op., at 8)
- (Souter, J., concurring).
-
-
-
- B
- Some have challenged this precedent by reading the
- Establishment Clause to permit -nonpreferential- state
- promotion of religion. The challengers argue that, as
- originally understood by the Framers, -[t]he Establishment
- Clause did not require government neutrality between
- religion and irreligion nor did it prohibit the Federal
- Government from providing nondiscriminatory aid to
- religion.- Wallace, supra, at 106 (Rehnquist, J., dissent-
- ing); see also R. Cord, Separation of Church and State:
- Historical Fact and Current Fiction (1988). While a case
- has been made for this position, it is not so convincing as to
- warrant reconsideration of our settled law; indeed, I find in
- the history of the Clause's textual development a more
- powerful argument supporting the Court's jurisprudence
- following Everson.
- When James Madison arrived at the First Congress with
- a series of proposals to amend the National Constitution,
- one of the provisions read that -[t]he civil rights of none
- shall be abridged on account of religious belief or worship,
- nor shall any national religion be established, nor shall the
- full and equal rights of conscience be in any manner, or on
- any pretext, infringed.- 1 Annals of Cong. 434 (1789).
- Madison's language did not last long. It was sent to a
- Select Committee of the House, which, without explanation,
- changed it to read that -no religion shall be established by
- law, nor shall the equal rights of conscience be infringed.-
- Id., at 729. Thence the proposal went to the Committee of
- the Whole, which was in turn dissatisfied with the Select
- Committee's language and adopted an alternative proposed
- by Samuel Livermore of New Hampshire: -Congress shall
- make no laws touching religion, or infringing the rights of
- conscience.- See id., at 731. Livermore's proposal would
- have forbidden laws having anything to do with religion
- and was thus not only far broader than Madison's version,
- but broader even than the scope of the Establishment
- Clause as we now understand it. See, e.g., Corporation of
- Presiding Bishop of Church of Jesus Christ of Latter-Day
- Saints v. Amos, 483 U. S. 327 (1987) (upholding legislative
- exemption of religious groups from certain obligations under
- civil rights laws).
- The House rewrote the amendment once more before
- sending it to the Senate, this time adopting, without
- recorded debate, language derived from a proposal by
- Fisher Ames of Massachusetts: -Congress shall make no
- law establishing Religion, or prohibiting the free exercise
- thereof, nor shall the rights of conscience be infringed.- 1
- Documentary History of the First Federal Congress of the
- United States of America 136 (Senate Journal) (L. de Pauw
- ed. 1972); see 1 Annals of Cong. 765 (1789). Perhaps, on
- further reflection, the Representatives had thought Liver-
- more's proposal too expansive, or perhaps, as one historian
- has suggested, they had simply worried that his language
- would not -satisfy the demands of those who wanted
- something said specifically against establishments of
- religion.- L. Levy, The Establishment Clause 81 (1986)
- (hereinafter Levy). We do not know; what we do know is
- that the House rejected the Select Committee's version,
- which arguably ensured only that -no religion- enjoyed an
- official preference over others, and deliberately chose
- instead a prohibition extending to laws establishing
- -religion- in general.
- The sequence of the Senate's treatment of this House
- proposal, and the House's response to the Senate, confirm
- that the Framers meant the Establishment Clause's
- prohibition to encompass nonpreferential aid to religion. In
- September 1789, the Senate considered a number of
- provisions that would have permitted such aid, and ulti-
- mately it adopted one of them. First, it briefly entertained
- this language: -Congress shall make no law establishing
- One Religious Sect or Society in preference to others, nor
- shall the rights of conscience be infringed.- 1 Documentary
- History, supra, at 151 (Senate Journal). After rejecting two
- minor amendments to that proposal, see ibid., the Senate
- dropped it altogether and chose a provision identical to the
- House's proposal, but without the clause protecting the
- -rights of conscience,- ibid. With no record of the Senate
- debates, we cannot know what prompted these changes, but
- the record does tell us that, six days later, the Senate went
- half circle and adopted its narrowest language yet: -Con-
- gress shall make no law establishing articles of faith or a
- mode of worship, or prohibiting the free exercise of reli-
- gion.- Id., at 166. The Senate sent this proposal to the
- House along with its versions of the other constitutional
- amendments proposed.
- Though it accepted much of the Senate's work on the Bill
- of Rights, the House rejected the Senate's version of the
- Establishment Clause and called for a joint conference
- committee, to which the Senate agreed. The House
- conferees ultimately won out, persuading the Senate to
- accept this as the final text of the Religion Clauses:
- -Congress shall make no law respecting an establishment
- of religion, or prohibiting the free exercise thereof.- What
- is remarkable is that, unlike the earliest House drafts or
- the final Senate proposal, the prevailing language is not
- limited to laws respecting an establishment of -a religion,-
- -a national religion,- -one religious sect,- or specific -articles
- of faith.- The Framers repeatedly considered and deliber-
- ately rejected such narrow language and instead extended
- their prohibition to state support for -religion- in general.
- Implicit in their choice is the distinction between prefer-
- ential and nonpreferential establishments, which the weight
- of evidence suggests the Framers appreciated. See, e.g.,
- Laycock, -Nonpreferential- Aid 902-906; Levy 91-119. But
- cf. T. Curry, The First Freedoms 208-222 (1986). Of
- particular note, the Framers were vividly familiar with
- efforts in the colonies and, later, the States to impose
- general, nondenominational assessments and other inci-
- dents of ostensibly ecumenical establishments. See gener-
- ally Levy 1-62. The Virginia Statute for Religious Free-
- dom, written by Jefferson and sponsored by Madison,
- captured the separationist response to such measures.
- Condemning all establishments, however nonpreferentialist,
- the Statute broadly guaranteed that -no man shall be
- compelled to frequent or support any religious worship,
- place, or ministry whatsoever,- including his own. Act for
- Establishing Religious Freedom (1785), in 5 The Founders'
- Constitution 84, 85 (P. Kurland & R. Lerner eds. 1987).
- Forcing a citizen to support even his own church would,
- among other things, deny -the ministry those temporary
- rewards, which proceeding from an approbation of their
- personal conduct, are an additional incitement to earnest
- and unremitting labours for the instruction of mankind.-
- Id, at 84. In general, Madison later added, -religion &
- Govt. will both exist in greater purity, the less they are
- mixed together.- Letter from J. Madison to E. Livingston,
- 10 July 1822, in 5 The Founders' Constitution, at 105, 106.
- What we thus know of the Framers' experience under-
- scores the observation of one prominent commentator, that
- confining the Establishment Clause to a prohibition on
- preferential aid -requires a premise that the Framers were
- extraordinarily bad drafters-that they believed one thing
- but adopted language that said something substantially
- different, and that they did so after repeatedly attending to
- the choice of language.- Laycock, ``Nonpreferential'' Aid
- 882-883; see also Allegheny County v. American Civil
- Liberties Union, Greater Pittsburgh Chapter, 492 U. S. 573,
- 647-648 (1989) (opinion of Stevens, J.). We must presume,
- since there is no conclusive evidence to the contrary, that
- the Framers embraced the significance of their textual judg-
- ment. Thus, on balance, history neither contradicts nor
- warrants reconsideration of the settled principle that the
- Establishment Clause forbids support for religion in general
- no less than support for one religion or some.
-
- C
- While these considerations are, for me, sufficient to reject
- the nonpreferentialist position, one further concern ani-
- mates my judgment. In many contexts, including this one,
- nonpreferentialism requires some distinction between
- -sectarian- religious practices and those that would be, by
- some measure, ecumenical enough to pass Establishment
- Clause muster. Simply by requiring the enquiry, nonprefer-
- entialists invite the courts to engage in comparative
- theology. I can hardly imagine a subject less amenable to
- the competence of the federal judiciary, or more deliberately
- to be avoided where possible.
- This case is nicely in point. Since the nonpreferentiality
- of a prayer must be judged by its text, Justice Blackmun
- pertinently observes, ante, at 6, n. 5, that Rabbi Gutterman
- drew his exhortation -[t]o do justly, to love mercy, to walk
- humbly- straight from the King James version of Micah, ch.
- 6, v. 8. At some undefinable point, the similarities between
- a state-sponsored prayer and the sacred text of a specific
- religion would so closely identify the former with the latter
- that even a nonpreferentialist would have to concede a
- breach of the Establishment Clause. And even if Micah's
- thought is sufficiently generic for most believers, it still
- embodies a straightforwardly Theistic premise, and so does
- the Rabbi's prayer. Many Americans who consider them-
- selves religious are not Theistic; some, like several of the
- Framers, are Deists who would question Rabbi Gutterman's
- plea for divine advancement of the country's political and
- moral good. Thus, a nonpreferentialist who would condemn
- subjecting public school graduates to, say, the Anglican
- liturgy would still need to explain why the government's
- preference for Theistic over non-Theistic religion is
- constitutional.
- Nor does it solve the problem to say that the State should
- promote a -diversity- of religious views; that position would
- necessarily compel the government and, inevitably, the
- courts to make wholly inappropriate judgments about the
- number of religions the State should sponsor and the
- relative frequency with which it should sponsor each. In
- fact, the prospect would be even worse than that. As
- Madison observed in criticizing religious presidential
- proclamations, the practice of sponsoring religious messages
- tends, over time, -to narrow the recommendation to the
- standard of the predominant sect.- Madison's -Detached
- Memoranda,- 3 Wm. & Mary Q. 534, 561 (E. Fleet ed. 1946)
- (hereinafter Madison's ``Detached Memoranda''). We have
- not changed much since the days of Madison, and the
- judiciary should not willingly enter the political arena to
- battle the centripetal force leading from religious pluralism
- to official preference for the faith with the most votes.
-
- II
- Petitioners rest most of their argument on a theory that,
- whether or not the Establishment Clause permits extensive
- nonsectarian support for religion, it does not forbid the
- state to sponsor affirmations of religious belief that coerce
- neither support for religion nor participation in religious
- observance. I appreciate the force of some of the arguments
- supporting a -coercion- analysis of the Clause. See gener-
- ally Allegheny County, supra, at 655-679 (opinion of
- Kennedy, J.); McConnell, Coercion: The Lost Element of
- Establishment, 27 Wm. & Mary L. Rev. 933 (1986). But we
- could not adopt that reading without abandoning our
- settled law, a course that, in my view, the text of the
- Clause would not readily permit. Nor does the extratextual
- evidence of original meaning stand so unequivocally at odds
- with the textual premise inherent in existing precedent that
- we should fundamentally reconsider our course.
-
- A
- Over the years, this Court has declared the invalidity of
- many noncoercive state laws and practices conveying a
- message of religious endorsement. For example, in Alle-
- gheny County, supra, we forbade the prominent display of
- a nativity scene on public property; without contesting the
- dissent's observation that the cr-che coerced no one into
- accepting or supporting whatever message it proclaimed,
- five Members of the Court found its display unconstitu-
- tional as a state endorsement of Christianity. Id., at
- 589-594, 598-602. Likewise, in Wallace v. Jaffree, 472
- U. S. 38 (1985), we struck down a state law requiring a
- moment of silence in public classrooms not because the
- statute coerced students to participate in prayer (for it did
- not), but because the manner of its enactment -convey[ed]
- a message of state approval of prayer activities in the public
- schools.- Id., at 61; see also id., at 67-84 (O'Connor, J.,
- concurring in judgment). Cf. Engel v. Vitale, 370 U. S., at
- 431 (-When the power, prestige and financial support of
- government is placed behind a particular religious belief,
- the indirect coercive pressure upon religious minorities to
- conform to the prevailing officially approved religion is
- plain. But the purposes underlying the Establishment
- Clause go much further than that-).
- In Epperson v. Arkansas, 393 U. S. 97 (1968), we invali-
- dated a state law that barred the teaching of Darwin's
- theory of evolution because, even though the statute
- obviously did not coerce anyone to support religion or
- participate in any religious practice, it was enacted for a
- singularly religious purpose. See also Edwards v.
- Aguillard, 482 U. S. 578, 593 (1987) (statute requiring
- instruction in -creation science- -endorses religion in
- violation of the First Amendment-). And in School Dist. of
- Grand Rapids v. Ball, 473 U. S. 373 (1985), we invalidated
- a program whereby the State sent public school teachers to
- parochial schools to instruct students on ostensibly nonreli-
- gious matters; while the scheme clearly did not coerce
- anyone to receive or subsidize religious instruction, we held
- it invalid because, among other things, -[t]he symbolic
- union of church and state inherent in the [program]
- threatens to convey a message of state support for religion
- to students and to the general public.- Id., at 397; see also
- Texas Monthly, Inc. v. Bullock, 489 U. S., at 17 (plurality
- opinion) (tax exemption benefiting only religious publica-
- tions -effectively endorses religious belief-); id., at 28
- (Blackmun, J., concurring in judgment) (exemption
- unconstitutional because State -engaged in preferential
- support for the communication of religious messages-).
- Our precedents may not always have drawn perfectly
- straight lines. They simply cannot, however, support the
- position that a showing of coercion is necessary to a
- successful Establishment Clause claim.
-
- B
- Like the provisions about -due- process and -unreason-
- able- searches and seizures, the constitutional language
- forbidding laws -respecting an establishment of religion- is
- not pellucid. But virtually everyone acknowledges that the
- Clause bans more than formal establishments of religion in
- the traditional sense, that is, massive state support for
- religion through, among other means, comprehensive
- schemes of taxation. See generally Levy 1-62 (discussing
- such establishments in the colonies and early States). This
- much follows from the Framers' explicit rejection of simpler
- provisions prohibiting either the establishment of a religion
- or laws -establishing religion- in favor of the broader ban
- on laws -respecting an establishment of religion.- See
- supra, at 4-6.
- While some argue that the Framers added the word
- -respecting- simply to foreclose federal interference with
- State establishments of religion, see, e.g., Amar, The Bill of
- Rights as a Constitution, 100 Yale L. J. 1131, 1157 (1991),
- the language sweeps more broadly than that. In Madison's
- words, the Clause in its final form forbids -everything like-
- a national religious establishment, see Madison's -Detached
- Memoranda- 558, and, after incorporation, it forbids
- -everything like- a State religious establishment. Cf.
- Allegheny County, 492 U. S., at 649 (opinion of Stevens,
- J.). The sweep is broad enough that Madison himself
- characterized congressional provisions for legislative and
- military chaplains as unconstitutional -establishments.-
- Madison's -Detached Memoranda- 558-559; see infra, at
- 16-17, and n. 6.
- While petitioners insist that the prohibition extends only
- to the -coercive- features and incidents of establishment,
- they cannot easily square that claim with the constitutional
- text. The First Amendment forbids not just laws -respect-
- ing an establishment of religion,- but also those -prohibiting
- the free exercise thereof.- Yet laws that coerce nonadher-
- ents to -support or participate in any religion or its exer-
- cise,- Allegheny County, supra, at 659-660 (opinion of
- Kennedy, J.), would virtually by definition violate their
- right to religious free exercise. See Employment Div., Dept.
- of Human Resources of Ore. v. Smith, 494 U. S. 872, 877
- (1990) (under Free Exercise Clause, -government may not
- compel affirmation of religious belief-), citing Torcaso v.
- Watkins, 367 U. S. 488 (1961); see also J. Madison, Memori-
- al and Remonstrance Against Religious Assessments (1785)
- (compelling support for religious establishments violates
- -free exercise of Religion-), quoted in 5 The Founders'
- Constitution, at 82, 84. Thus, a literal application of the
- coercion test would render the Establishment Clause a vir-
- tual nullity, as petitioners' counsel essentially conceded at
- oral argument. Tr. of Oral Arg. 18.
- Our cases presuppose as much; as we said in School Dist.
- of Abington, supra, -[t]he distinction between the two
- clauses is apparent-a violation of the Free Exercise Clause
- is predicated on coercion while the Establishment Clause
- violation need not be so attended.- 374 U. S., at 223; see
- also Laycock, ``Nonpreferential'' Aid 922 (-If coercion is . . .
- an element of the establishment clause, establishment adds
- nothing to free exercise-). While one may argue that the
- Framers meant the Establishment Clause simply to
- ornament the First Amendment, cf. T. Curry, The First
- Freedoms 216-217 (1986), that must be a reading of last
- resort. Without compelling evidence to the contrary, we
- should presume that the Framers meant the Clause to
- stand for something more than petitioners attribute to it.
-
-
- C
- Petitioners argue from the political setting in which the
- Establishment Clause was framed, and from the Framers'
- own political practices following ratification, that govern-
- ment may constitutionally endorse religion so long as it
- does not coerce religious conformity. The setting and the
- practices warrant canvassing, but while they yield some
- evidence for petitioners' argument, they do not reveal the
- degree of consensus in early constitutional thought that
- would raise a threat to stare decisis by challenging the pre-
- sumption that the Establishment Clause adds something to
- the Free Exercise Clause that follows it.
- The Framers adopted the Religion Clauses in response to
- a long tradition of coercive state support for religion,
- particularly in the form of tax assessments, but their
- special antipathy to religious coercion did not exhaust their
- hostility to the features and incidents of establishment.
- Indeed, Jefferson and Madison opposed any political appro-
- priation of religion, see infra, at 15-18 and, even when
- challenging the hated assessments, they did not always
- temper their rhetoric with distinctions between coercive and
- noncoercive state action. When, for example, Madison
- criticized Virginia's general assessment bill, he invoked
- principles antithetical to all state efforts to promote
- religion. An assessment, he wrote, is improper not simply
- because it forces people to donate -three pence- to religion,
- but, more broadly, because -it is itself a signal of persecu-
- tion. It degrades from the equal rank of Citizens all those
- whose opinions in Religion do not bend to those of the
- Legislative authority.- J. Madison, Memorial and Remon-
- strance Against Religious Assessments (1785), in 5 The
- Founders' Constitution, at 83. Madison saw that, even
- without the tax collector's participation, an official endorse-
- ment of religion can impair religious liberty.
- Petitioners contend that because the early Presidents
- included religious messages in their inaugural and Thanks-
- giving Day addresses, the Framers could not have meant
- the Establishment Clause to forbid noncoercive state
- endorsement of religion. The argument ignores the fact,
- however, that Americans today find such proclamations less
- controversial than did the founding generation, whose
- published thoughts on the matter belie petitioners' claim.
- President Jefferson, for example, steadfastly refused to
- issue Thanksgiving proclamations of any kind, in part
- because he thought they violated the Religion Clauses.
- Letter from Thomas Jefferson to Rev. S. Miller (Jan. 23,
- 1808), in 5 The Founders' Constitution, at 98. In explaining
- his views to the Reverend Samuel Miller, Jefferson effec-
- tively anticipated, and rejected, petitioners' position:
- ``[I]t is only proposed that I should recommend, not
- prescribe a day of fasting & prayer. That is, that I
- should indirectly assume to the U. S. an authority over
- religious exercises which the Constitution has directly
- precluded from them. It must be meant too that this
- recommendation is to carry some authority, and to be
- sanctioned by some penalty on those who disregard it;
- not indeed of fine and imprisonment, but of some
- degree of proscription perhaps in public opinion.'' Id.,
- at 98-99 (emphasis in original).
- By condemning such noncoercive state practices that, in
- -recommending- the majority faith, demean religious
- dissenters -in public opinion,- Jefferson necessarily con-
- demned what, in modern terms, we call official endorse-
- ment of religion. He accordingly construed the Establish-
- ment Clause to forbid not simply state coercion, but also
- state endorsement, of religious belief and observance. And
- if he opposed impersonal presidential addresses for in-
- flicting -proscription in public opinion,- all the more would
- he have condemned less diffuse expressions of official
- endorsement.
- During his first three years in office, James Madison also
- refused to call for days of thanksgiving and prayer, though
- later, amid the political turmoil of the War of 1812, he did
- so on four separate occasions. See Madison's -Detached
- Memoranda,- 562, and n. 54. Upon retirement, in an essay
- condemning as an unconstitutional -establishment- the use
- of public money to support congressional and military
- chaplains, id., at 558-560, he concluded that -[r]eligious
- proclamations by the Executive recommending thanksgiv-
- ings & fasts are shoots from the same root with the
- legislative acts reviewed. Altho' recommendations only,
- they imply a religious agency, making no part of the trust
- delegated to political rulers.- Id., at 560. Explaining that
- -[t]he members of a Govt . . . can in no sense, be regarded
- as possessing an advisory trust from their Constituents in
- their religious capacities,- ibid., he further observed that
- the state necessarily freights all of its religious messages
- with political ones: -the idea of policy [is] associated with
- religion, whatever be the mode or the occasion, when a
- function of the latter is assumed by those in power.- Id., at
- 562 (footnote omitted).
- Madison's failure to keep pace with his principles in the
- face of congressional pressure cannot erase the principles.
- He admitted to backsliding, and explained that he had
- made the content of his wartime proclamations inconse-
- quential enough to mitigate much of their impropriety. See
- ibid.; see also Letter from J. Madison to E. Livingston (July
- 10, 1822), in 5 The Founders' Constitution, at 105. While
- his writings suggest mild variations in his interpretation of
- the Establishment Clause, Madison was no different in that
- respect from the rest of his political generation. That he
- expressed so much doubt about the constitutionality of
- religious proclamations, however, suggests a brand of
- separationism stronger even than that embodied in our
- traditional jurisprudence. So too does his characterization
- of public subsidies for legislative and military chaplains as
- unconstitutional -establishments,- see supra, at 16-17, and
- n. 6, for the federal courts, however expansive their general
- view of the Establishment Clause, have upheld both
- practices. See Marsh v. Chambers, 463 U. S. 783 (1983)
- (legislative chaplains); Katcoff v. Marsh, 755 F. 2d 223 (CA2
- 1985) (military chaplains).
- To be sure, the leaders of the young Republic engaged in
- some of the practices that separationists like Jefferson and
- Madison criticized. The First Congress did hire institu-
- tional chaplains, see Marsh v. Chambers, supra, at 788, and
- Presidents Washington and Adams unapologetically marked
- days of ``public thanksgiving and prayer,'' see R. Cord,
- Separation of Church and State 53 (1988). Yet in the face
- of the separationist dissent, those practices prove, at best,
- that the Framers simply did not share a common under-
- standing of the Establishment Clause, and, at worst, that
- they, like other politicians, could raise constitutional ideals
- one day and turn their backs on them the next. -Indeed, by
- 1787 the provisions of the state bills of rights had become
- what Madison called mere `paper parchments'-expressions
- of the most laudable sentiments, observed as much in the
- breach as in practice.- Kurland, The Origins of the Religion
- Clauses of the Constitution, 27 Wm. & Mary L. Rev. 839,
- 852 (1986) (footnote omitted). Sometimes the National
- Constitution fared no better. Ten years after proposing the
- First Amendment, Congress passed the Alien and Sedition
- Acts, measures patently unconstitutional by modern
- standards. If the early Congress's political actions were
- determinative, and not merely relevant, evidence of consti-
- tutional meaning, we would have to gut our current First
- Amendment doctrine to make room for political censorship.
- While we may be unable to know for certain what the
- Framers meant by the Clause, we do know that, around the
- time of its ratification, a respectable body of opinion
- supported a considerably broader reading than petitioners
- urge upon us. This consistency with the textual consider-
- ations is enough to preclude fundamentally reexamining our
- settled law, and I am accordingly left with the task of
- considering whether the state practice at issue here violates
- our traditional understanding of the Clause's proscriptions.
-
- III
- While the Establishment Clause's concept of neutrality is
- not self-revealing, our recent cases have invested it with
- specific content: the state may not favor or endorse either
- religion generally over nonreligion or one religion over
- others. See, e.g., Allegheny County, 492 U. S., at 589-594,
- 598-602; Texas Monthly, 489 U. S., at 17 (plurality opin-
- ion); id., at 28 (Blackmun, J., concurring in judgment);
- Edwards v. Aguillard, 482 U. S., at 593; School Dist. of
- Grand Rapids, 473 U. S., at 389-392; Wallace v. Jaffree,
- 472 U. S., at 61; see also Laycock, Formal, Substantive, and
- Disaggregated Neutrality Toward Religion, 39 De Paul L.
- Rev. 993 (1990); cf. Lemon v. Kurtzman, 403 U. S. 602,
- 612-613 (1971). This principle against favoritism and
- endorsement has become the foundation of Establishment
- Clause jurisprudence, ensuring that religious belief is
- irrelevant to every citizen's standing in the political
- community, see Allegheny County, supra, at 594; J. Madi-
- son, Memorial and Remonstrance Against Religious Assess-
- ments (1785), in 5 The Founders' Constitution, at 82-83,
- and protecting religion from the demeaning effects of any
- governmental embrace, see id., at 83. Now, as in the early
- Republic, -religion & Govt. will both exist in greater purity,
- the less they are mixed together.- Letter from J. Madison
- to E. Livingston (10 July 1822), in 5 The Founders' Consti-
- tution, at 106. Our aspiration to religious liberty, embodied
- in the First Amendment, permits no other standard.
-
- A
- That government must remain neutral in matters of
- religion does not foreclose it from ever taking religion into
- account. The State may -accommodate- the free exercise of
- religion by relieving people from generally applicable rules
- that interfere with their religious callings. See, e.g.,
- Corporation of Presiding Bishop of Church of Jesus Christ
- of Latter-Day Saints v. Amos, 483 U. S. 327 (1987); see also
- Sherbert v. Verner, 374 U. S. 398 (1963). Contrary to the
- views of some, such accommodation does not necessarily
- signify an official endorsement of religious observance over
- disbelief.
- In everyday life, we routinely accommodate religious
- beliefs that we do not share. A Christian inviting an
- Orthodox Jew to lunch might take pains to choose a kosher
- restaurant; an atheist in a hurry might yield the right of
- way to an Amish man steering a horse-drawn carriage. In
- so acting, we express respect for, but not endorsement of,
- the fundamental values of others. We act without express-
- ing a position on the theological merit of those values or of
- religious belief in general, and no one perceives us to have
- taken such a position.
- The government may act likewise. Most religions
- encourage devotional practices that are at once crucial to
- the lives of believers and idiosyncratic in the eyes of
- nonadherents. By definition, secular rules of general
- application are drawn from the nonadherent's vantage and,
- consequently, fail to take such practices into account. Yet
- when enforcement of such rules cuts across religious
- sensibilities, as it often does, it puts those affected to the
- choice of taking sides between God and government. In
- such circumstances, accommodating religion reveals nothing
- beyond a recognition that general rules can unnecessarily
- offend the religious conscience when they offend the
- conscience of secular society not at all. Cf. Welsh v. United
- States, 398 U. S. 333, 340 (1970) (plurality opinion). Thus,
- in freeing the Native American Church from federal laws
- forbidding peyote use, see Drug Enforcement Administra-
- tion Miscellaneous Exemptions, 21 C. F. R. 1307.31
- (1991), the government conveys no endorsement of peyote
- rituals, the Church, or religion as such; it simply respects
- the centrality of peyote to the lives of certain Americans.
- See Note, The Free Exercise Boundaries of Permissible
- Accommodation Under the Establishment Clause, 99 Yale
- L. J. 1127, 1135-1136 (1990).
-
- B
- Whatever else may define the scope of accommodation
- permissible under the Establishment Clause, one require-
- ment is clear: accommodation must lift a discernible
- burden on the free exercise of religion. See Allegheny
- County, supra, at 601, n. 51; id., at 631-632 (opinion of
- O'Connor, J.); Corporation of Presiding Bishop, supra, at
- 348 (O'Connor, J., concurring in judgment); see also Texas
- Monthly, supra, at 18, 18-19, n. 8 (plurality opinion);
- Wallace v. Jaffree, 472 U. S., at 57-58, n. 45. But see
- Allegheny County, supra, at 663, n. 2 (opinion of Kennedy,
- J.). Concern for the position of religious individuals in the
- modern regulatory state cannot justify official solicitude for
- a religious practice unburdened by general rules; such
- gratuitous largesse would effectively favor religion over
- disbelief. By these lights one easily sees that, in sponsoring
- the graduation prayers at issue here, the State has crossed
- the line from permissible accommodation to unconstitution-
- al establishment.
- Religious students cannot complain that omitting prayers
- from their graduation ceremony would, in any realistic
- sense, -burden- their spiritual callings. To be sure, many
- of them invest this rite of passage with spiritual signifi-
- cance, but they may express their religious feelings about
- it before and after the ceremony. They may even organize
- a privately sponsored baccalaureate if they desire the
- company of likeminded students. Because they accordingly
- have no need for the machinery of the State to affirm their
- beliefs, the government's sponsorship of prayer at the
- graduation ceremony is most reasonably understood as an
- official endorsement of religion and, in this instance, of
- Theistic religion. One may fairly say, as one commentator
- has suggested, that the government brought prayer into the
- ceremony -precisely because some people want a symbolic
- affirmation that government approves and endorses their
- religion, and because many of the people who want this
- affirmation place little or no value on the costs to religious
- minorities.- Laycock, Summary and Synthesis: The Crisis
- in Religious Liberty, 60 Geo. Wash. L. Rev. 841, 844
- (1992).
- Petitioners would deflect this conclusion by arguing that
- graduation prayers are no different from presidential
- religious proclamations and similar official -acknowledg-
- ments- of religion in public life. But religious invocations
- in Thanksgiving Day addresses and the like, rarely noticed,
- ignored without effort, conveyed over an impersonal
- medium, and directed at no one in particular, inhabit a
- pallid zone worlds apart from official prayers delivered to a
- captive audience of public school students and their
- families. Madison himself respected the difference between
- the trivial and the serious in constitutional practice.
- Realizing that his contemporaries were unlikely to take the
- Establishment Clause seriously enough to forgo a legislative
- chaplainship, he suggested that -[r]ather than let this step
- beyond the landmarks of power have the effect of a legiti-
- mate precedent, it will be better to apply to it the legal
- aphorism de minimis non curat lex . . . .- Madison's
- -Detached Memoranda- 559; see also Letter from J. Madi-
- son to E. Livingston, 10 July 1822, in 5 The Founders'
- Constitution, at 105. But that logic permits no winking at
- the practice in question here. When public school officials,
- armed with the State's authority, convey an endorsement of
- religion to their students, they strike near the core of the
- Establishment Clause. However -ceremonial- their mes-
- sages may be, they are flatly unconstitutional.
-